Anthropology as
Anti-Colonial Protest
In
the same critical spirit of Lévi-Strauss,
Jorgensen and Wolf point out that anthropology
has another side to it. They argue that,
“in the tradition of Montaigne and Rousseau,
[anthropologists] radically questioned the
pretensions to superiority of Western
civilization, while seeking alternative
visions of man. This latter aspect of the
anthropological consciousness has always
been recognized in the United States, to the
enduring credit of such men as Franz Boas,
Robert Redfield, and Paul Radin. Throughout
the history of the profession
anthropologists have condemned the assault
of the American government on American
Indians (although the ‘solutions’ they
suggested were not, and perhaps could not
have been, better than those from any other
source); and the Association has defended
the social and cultural rights of minority
peoples, and taken early and unequivocal
positions against fascism and racism. The
Nazis, it should be noted, understood this
aspect of the discipline in Europe and
systematically sought to cut the heart out
of German anthropology, reducing it to a
reflex of the regime”.
Jorgensen and Wolf thus raise the relativist
tradition in anthropology, and they specifically
refer to Montaigne and Rousseau.
Jorgensen and Wolf end their article by stating,
“Admittedly, anthropology was ambiguously
conceived”. It’s not very clear to me that in
its conception in the US and UK there was
notable ambiguity, especially given the strong
mark of polygenesis and scientific racism both
in the Anthropological Society of London, and in
the American School of Ethnology during the
mid-1800s, as anthropology was being conceived
before it became fully professionalized.
Thinking about alternatives, Jorgensen and Wolf
state that, “in our view, [anthropology] must
disengage itself from its connection with
colonial aims or it will become intellectually
trivial.” For me this is both a positive goal
and a subtle shift in their message. By this
point in their article they have completely
dropped any discussion of the epistemology of
the discipline, how the structures of thought
inherent to anthropology and its “credibility”
(their word) are rooted in an objectivity that
is itself rendered operational by the colonial
experience. They certainly do conceive of an
altered role for anthropology, however, which I
support even if I am not clear as to the extent
to which they took up this role themselves:
“Anthropologists must be willing to testify in
behalf of the oppressed peoples of the world,
including those whom we professionally define as
primitives and peasants”. Expert witnesses,
speaking in defence of the oppressed would seem
to be a critically important role. This still
leaves some questions open: from where does
their expertise spring? What marks their
expertise as “anthropological” as different from
the testimony of others? And why do “we” need
experts to mediate when the oppressed often do,
can, and demand to speak for themselves?
An Anti-Imperial
Tradition?
Jorgensen and Wolf raised the figure of
Michel de Montaigne, speaking to the
roots of cultural relativism in anthropology,
and the radical critique of Western superiority
that they believe they saw resting within
anthropology. In the past I have had occasion to
read and use Montaigne’s famous essay, “Of
Cannibals” ([1578-1580]). I was
especially impressed by his introduction of
Brazilian indigenous commentary on French
society, thanks to three Brazilian Indians
brought to France. They provide a rare
commentary for the colonial epoch, and a strong
critique of imperial society, noting first that
it was amazing that the men they met submitted
to a monarch who was little more than a child,
and then this: “they had observed, that there
were among us men full and crammed with all
manner of commodities, while, in the meantime,
their halves were begging at their doors, lean,
and half-starved with hunger and poverty; and
they thought it strange that these necessitous
halves were able to suffer so great an
inequality and injustice, and that they did not
take the others by the throats, or set fire to
their houses”.
Richard Handler has written [(1986). “Of
cannibals and custom: Montaigne’s cultural
relativism”. Anthropology Today, Vol. 2,
No. 5 (Oct), pp. 12–14] a very relevant
critical, yet sympathetic analysis of some of
the contradictions within the work of Montaigne,
which could in fact not only undo Montaigne’s
own theses, while providing support for
criticisms of cultural relativism, but they also
betray one critically important approach marking
all anthropology and subjected to a withering
critique by Vassos Argyrou. Montaigne’s argument
is, in Handler’s words, that “we justify what
are necessarily relative ideas—that is, those
that come to us via customs—absolutes” (Handler,
1986, p. 12). Handler quotes at length from
Montaigne’s essay, “Of
Custom”. I will quote the same passage
from a translation different than the one
available to Handler, simply because it is the
one that is available to all interested readers:
“The laws of conscience, which we pretend to
be derived from nature, proceed from custom;
every one, having an inward veneration for
the opinions and manners approved and
received among his own people, cannot,
without very great reluctance, depart from
them, nor apply himself to them without
applause. In times past, when those of Crete
would curse any one, they prayed the gods to
engage him in some ill custom. But the
principal effect of its power is, so to
seize and ensnare us, that it is hardly in
us to disengage ourselves from its gripe, or
so to come to ourselves, as to consider of
and to weigh the things it enjoins. To say
the truth, by reason that we suck it in with
our milk, and that the face of the world
presents itself in this posture to our first
sight, it seems as if we were born upon
condition to follow on this track; and the
common fancies that we find in repute
everywhere about us, and infused into our
minds with the seed of our fathers, appear
to be the most universal and genuine: from
whence it comes to pass, that whatever is
off the hinges of custom, is believed to be
also off the hinges of reason; how
unreasonably, for the most part, God knows”.
As
Handler explains, what Montaigne is doing here
is arguing what has become a central thesis in
relativist anthropology: that people naturalize
arbitrary cultural constructs, mistaking the
relativity of customs for absolutes of “nature”
or “reason”. According to Handler, Montaigne
argues that “humans do not easily recognize the
element of bias that inevitably accompanies a
culturally particular worldview—that is, that
humans more frequently defend, with whatever
arguments are at hand, than criticize or
relativize their customary orientation to the
world” (Handler, 1986, p. 12).
The
first ambiguity, if not outright contradiction
that Handler finds, lies in Montaigne’s
retention of an assumption of an absolute and
universal reason. As Handler explains, “to say
that people unreasonably mistake ‘what is
off the hinges of custom’ for ‘what is off the
hinges of reason’ is to suggest that despite the
natives’ confusion of custom and reason, there
nonetheless exists some absolute faculty of
reason by which, if they appealed to it, they
could avoid their confusion” (Handler, 1986, p.
13). Thus, despite Montaigne underlining the
power of custom to shape reason itself, “he
refuses to relinquish a notion of reason
understood as a culturally neutral faculty
capable of impartial judgment” (Handler, 1986,
p. 13). There is yet another way of explaining
this “contradiction,” and it will come up again
when we talk about Argyrou, and that is simply
this: where does Montaigne stand that is
dominated by pure reason and is unaffected by
the arbitrary power of custom?
Without Any Difference
As
Handler points out, Montaigne’s thinking gives
weight to the Enlightenment belief in universal
reason—reason that is the same for all persons
and all cultures at all times: “In Montaigne,
reason similarly takes on universalistic
implications, since in spite of his insistence
on the diversity of custom, he reserves a place
for reason—at least for ‘reasonable’
reason—above and beyond custom, a reason that
can transcend custom and judge it” (Handler,
1986, p. 13). The crucial point to observe here
is that when your logic guarantees such
universal human unity, your interpretation of
cultural differences is that they are mere
surface phenomena: same contents, but different
form. In this regard, the relativist position
melts into the universalist one, and
anthropology becomes an exercise not in
“understanding” or “explaining” difference, but
rather just explaining it away.
Tzvetan Todorov [(1984). The Conquest of
America. New York: HarperCollins] also takes
issue with depictions of Amerindian cultural
difference as rooted in a basic, pristine human
nature that existed before the development of
civilization. Handler says that Todorov’s
argument is that this is a “superficially
charitable view of exotic others [that] does no
better than racism and ethnocentrism when it
comes to inter-cultural understanding” (Handler,
1986, p. 13). Handler reminds us of what
Montaigne says above, that even in defending
relativism he can only do so by way of an appeal
to an absolute human “nature”: the reason that
we suck in with our milk, that is infused in our
minds by the seed of the father (Handler, 1986,
p. 13).
What anthropologists know from cultural
evolutionists as the thesis of the
psychic unity of humankind found
earlier expression in Bartolomé de las Casas’
idea of the Christian unity of humankind: every
human can become a Christian (Todorov, 1984, p.
161). In the Papal Bull of 1537, Pope Paul III
reissued the declaration to “go forth and make
disciples of all nations,” because all are
capable of receiving Christ. “Without any
difference” becomes a critical component of las
Casas’ defense of the humanity of the
Amerindians (Todorov, 1984, p. 162). Christian
universalism implies an essential
non-difference among all humans, Todorov
explains. He points to a quote from Saint John
Chrysostom, used by las Casas in his debates at
Valldolid: “Just as there is no natural
difference in the creation of man, so there is
no difference in the call to salvation of all
men, barbarous or otherwise, since God’s grace
can correct the minds of barbarians, so that
they have a reasonable understanding” (quoted in
Todorov, 1984, p. 162). It’s a position that
helps las Casas to explain away
difference, when seemingly defending it: though
the Amerindians may appear to us to be
“indolent” and indifferent to wealth, that is
only because they still observe a basic
Christian virtue that we have forgotten, which
is to be content with no more than what is
necessary for survival.
Todorov’s critique of las Casas’ document,
Apologética Historia, is penetrating:
“If it is incontestable that the prejudice
of superiority is an obstacle in the road to
knowledge, we must also admit that the
prejudice of equality is a still greater
one, for it consists in identifying the
other purely and simply with one’s own ‘ego
ideal’ (or with oneself)”. (Todorov, 1984,
p. 165)
They may be different now, but
they will not always be so—this is
the perspective and the program being criticized
by Todorov. (It also seems apparent, Todorov
tells us, that las Casas could not live up to
his own universalist creed, as he “never shows
the slightest tenderness toward the Muslims” [p.
Todorov, 1984, 166].)
Handler adds that “in European history the
emergence of an anthropological ability to
understand others has not necessarily led to
compassionate interaction with them” (Handler,
1986, p. 13). Indeed, relying on Todorov, he
notes that cultural relativism can be enlisted
in the service of individualistic pragmatism,
where one uses one’s alleged understanding of
others in order to better manipulate others
(Handler, 1986, p. 13).
Handler’s key conclusion is that “a science of
others’ customs should not blind us to the
customary underpinnings of our own sciences”
(Handler, 1986, p. 14).
Can Anthropology
be Anti-Imperialist?
In
“New Proposals for Anthropologists” [(1968).
Current Anthropology, 9 (5): 403–435]
Kathleen Gough comments on the institutional
positioning of professional anthropologists (in
Europe and North America presumably) and how
this impacts on their place in a world
experiencing momentous upheavals. She writes:
“From the beginning, we have inhabited a
triple environment, involving obligations
first to the people we studied, second to
our colleagues and our science, and third to
the powers who employed us in universities
or who funded our research. In many cases we
seem now to be in danger of being torn apart
by the conflicts between the first and third
set of obligations, whiles the second set of
loyalties, to our subject as an objective
and humane endeavour, are being severely
tested and jeopardized”. (Gough, 1968, p.
405)
The
passage could have been written 40 years later
in another crisis decade that presents so many
reminders of her own. Some might argue about the
order of her list, or that those elements should
not even form discrete items in a list since
they are all tied to one another: the funding of
research is tied to the research of the people
we study, which is itself tied to our colleagues
who read our research or hire us to teach it.
Even then, Gough and others were reflecting on
what to do next in the face of worldwide crisis.
In fact she quotes a 1966 paper by Peter Worsley,
significantly titled, “The End of Anthropology?”
Her suggested direction, given that
specialization in small-scale societies is
losing currency in a world of rapidly expanding
scales of social interaction, is that we start
to study large-scale social systems. Then we
must be prepared for the fact that our work will
resemble that of political scientists,
economists, and sociologists. What we must do,
Gough urges, is to study “modern society as a
single, interdependent world social system”
(Gough, 1968, p. 405). This leads us to the
study of imperialism ultimately.
Why
have anthropologists not been at the forefront
of studies of imperialism, failing to study it
as a unitary phenomenon? One reason Gough
suggests is the impact of the process of
specialization within anthropology, and between
anthropology and the other disciplines. A second
reason is the tradition of fieldwork in
small-scale societies, which is simply the wrong
methodological basis for contemplating
overarching global phenomena such as
imperialism. A third is our general
unwillingness to offend the governments upon
whom we depend for funding and access. A fourth
reason is what she calls in the language of her
time, “the bureaucratic, counter-revolutionary
setting” in which anthropologists work in
universities, contributing to a sense of
impotence and reliance on machine-like models
(Gough, 1968, p. 406). (Updating her terms, we
would be speaking of the corporatization of the
university, the spread of neo-liberalism, the
chilling of academic freedom, and the push
toward business-relevant research.)
In
one broad sweep, Gough provides many useful
clues about the relationship between
anthropology and imperialism: (1) we do not
study imperialism, so that “critiquing” it
becomes more difficult, and unusual; (2) we
cannot study imperialism, because we have
the wrong methods; and, (3) we should not
study imperialism, because it might offend
sponsors and bosses, and could unseat us. Ironic
then, that the discipline that is
institutionalized in universities at the same
time as Euro-American imperialism reached new
giddy heights in the late 19th century, the
discipline that was imperialism’s traveling
companion if not scout, is the discipline that
is disarmed from studying the context, causes
and conditions of its own creation and current
existence. Anthropology is about the study of
others out of fear of facing ourselves? That
would be rather depressing, a kind of forced
narcissism.
Propositions
Thus far what we have encountered above are the
following issues relating anthropology to
empire:
(a)
the imperial nature of anthropology’s inherent
epistemology;
(b) the colonial positioning of anthropologists
in the field;
(c) the dependence on sponsorship by imperial
powers;
(d) a crisis of confidence regarding the nature
and purpose of our expertise; and,
(e) doubts about whether we ever have, or ever
could, actually understand difference.
We
already know that anthropology, as we have
learned it, is a Western construct. Anthropology
is a Western way of producing knowledge of the
world, based on many, disparate, small parts of
the world. It is also one Western way of
consuming the world. But it’s not simply a way
of gaining knowledge of the world, not the
anthropology that we have been taught. Nobody—no
students, no professors—can really say that the
only reason or the most important
reason that they entered anthropology is that
they were interested in just knowing more about
other cultures. It is not an innocent quest for
knowledge. One does not need degrees to learn
about other cultures, and learning about other
cultures does not lead to degrees (for most
humans). You may have a thirst for knowledge,
but something else is motivating you as well,
and that something else is of critical
importance. When one enrols in a degree program,
one is enlisting in an industrialized,
professionalized, system of production, one of
whose outputs is credentials and another being
power. Anthropology in institutions is not just
there to teach the world about the world: it is
there to teach a small club of society’s members
about the “right ways” of knowing that world.
Likewise, ethnography would seem to be the very
last candidate on a list of preferred, sane, and
humane ways of getting to know others. Getting
to know other people does not mean that we
intimately scrutinize them, document them in our
notes, and lay out their lives (according to the
accepted formulas) for an audience of specialist
surveyors, inspectors, and guardians of the
discipline. Wanting to share knowledge about
others should not mean that we think that only
we can explain others, and that we can even
explain others to themselves, like expert
demystifiers, who have risen above it all.
Otherwise it would seem absurd: those who taught
me about themselves, as I was ignorant about
them, need me to explain them to themselves?
However, it is not absurd, it is functionally
useful for maintaining the Westerner in the
position of protagonist. Anthropology as a
science is a way for the West to maintain its
imperial centrality in explaining the rest of
the world to the rest of the world. It teaches
the world that all legitimate and valid
interpretations of the world are to be made by
Westerners. Our appreciation for “science”
reflects our lust for influence and desire for
rewards. “Science” sells. Science develops
innovative means of control. Science offers us
better means of efficiently managing the
animals.
Some of the “big questions” asked by the Zero
Anthropology Project thus are:
•
Can a decolonized anthropology exist as
anthropology as we know it?
• Would not the real decolonization of
anthropology mean its termination and then
reconstruction?
• Would a decolonized anthropology even be
recognized as anthropology?
It
is not because of its mental endowments that
only the Western world has given birth to
anthropology, but rather because exotic
cultures, treated by us as mere things, could be
studied accordingly as things. Between our
attitude toward them and their attitude toward
us, there has been no parity. Lévi-Strauss put
this better than I have:
“Therefore, if native cultures are ever to
look at anthropology as a legitimate pursuit
and not as a sequel to the colonial era or
that of economic domination, it cannot
suffice for the players simply to change
camps while the anthropological game remains
the same. Anthropology itself must undergo a
deep transformation in order to carry on its
work among those cultures for whose study it
was intended because they lack a written
record of their history”. (Lévi-Strauss,
1966, p. 126)